Shiur #06: Difference in Obligation ofBeinAdamLe-chaveroandBein Adam La-Makom
Bein Adam Le-Chavero: Ethics of Interpersonal Conduct
By Rav Binyamin Zimmerman
******************************************************
This week’s shiurim are dedicated by Carole S. Daman of Scarsdale in memory
of Tzvi Hersh ben David Arye z”l – Harlan Daman
******************************************************
Shiur #06: Difference in Obligation of Bein
Adam Le-chavero
and Bein Adam La-Makom
The Two Basic Categories of Mitzvot:
In last week’s lesson we pointed out that although
many interpersonal mitzvot are rational, God chooses to command their
performance, essentially making them mitzvot bein adam la-Makom
(commandments dealing with one’s relationship with God).
If so, one might ask, what makes
these interpersonal directives, these mitzvot bein adam le-chavero
(commandments dealing with man and his fellow man) unique? Are they for all intents and purposes
really mitzvot bein adam la-Makom, with the only singularity being that
their fulfillment involves another, or are they fundamentally different in
nature?
While one may think that all mitzvot have
similar foundations, there are essential differences between mitzvot
bein adam le-chavero and mitzvot bein adam la-Makom. When we analyze the scope of
mitzvot and contrast these two categories of mitzvot, we can see that
they have differences that go beyond the foci of the action. By developing an
understanding of the distinctions between these two types of mitzvot, we
will hopefully reveal the unique nature of interpersonal directives.
We will attempt to draw a number of conclusions
based on the differences between mitzvot bein adam la-Makom and
mitzvot bein adam le-chavero on three levels, namely:
1.
The discrepancy in essential obligation.
2.
The divergent methods of rectifying violations of these commandments.
3.
The varying requirements for a birkat ha-mitzva, a blessing made
prior to the performance of the commandment.
The Discrepancy in Essential Obligation:
In general, understanding a mitzva requires
identifying its specific obligation.
Though the Torah instructs us to perform numerous mitzvot, analysis of
the nature of various laws indicates that not all mitzvot are created
equal. One can speak of at least
three types of obligations. Some
mitzvot are result- based, focusing on achieving the result the Torah
desires through the mitzva’s performance.
Other mitzvot are characterized by a focus on the outward action,
the maaseh, the mechanical act required by the Torah. There seems to exist a third category
as well, which combines the importance of a mechanical act (maaseh) with
a specific long-reaching aim or purpose; merged, these two elements achieve and
fulfill the essence of the commandment.
While each
mitzva should be analyzed independently, one does find a striking
bifurcation in the corpus of mitzvot, separating most mitzvot
bein adam la-Makom from their counterparts, mitzvot bein adam
le-chavero.
To better understand this distinction, let us begin
by discussing the need for kavana, the proper intent to perform a
mitzva in order to fulfill a
divine decree. The importance of
possessing kavana in order to properly execute certain mitzvot
seems to underscore the significance of the mindset accompanying the act, as
opposed to the result of the action.
The mitzva is not only a mere physical act, but an act performed with a
mitzva-directed frame of mind.
The Talmud, in a number of places, raises the issue
of whether mitzvot require kavana; i.e., is a commandment only
considered to be fulfilled if accompanied by the proper intent? The Mishna Berura (OC 60,
Beiur Halakha, s.v. Yesh) asserts that this debate only deals with
the necessity of kavana for the
mitzva, intent to perform the act as a commandment; however,
there is no doubt that one must have a certain type of kavana: the proper
intent for physical action. One who
manages to act out a mitzva without any thought whatsoever has the halakhic
status of mitasek, so this person is certainly not to be viewed as
fulfilling a mitzva, as the
Mishna Berura explains. The question
discussed in the Talmud is whether the intent to perform an action without
contemplating divine intent leaves one remiss in performing his or her duty.
This focus on the necessity of kavana seems
to indicate that at least some mitzvot are not merely designed to achieve
a certain result. After all, even if
the desired result is achieved through one’s action, the act is insignificant if
one lacks proper intention and mindset.
However, the Talmud does not stop there.
In at least two places, the Talmud indicates that the intent to perform a
mitzva, even without an actual execution, can be viewed as akin to the genuine
performance of the mitzva.
The Talmud (Berakhot 6a) expounds the
verse in Malakhi 3:16: “And it is written before Him… for those who think of His
name” that one who conceives of and intends to perform a mitzva but is unable to
do so due to circumstances beyond his control is considered to have performed
the mitzva.
In Kiddushin (40a), the Talmud refers to God
as joining the good thought to the unrealized act, so that one is rewarded as if
one had performed the mitzva.
The idea that kavana plays a role in our
favor, that the intent to perform a mitzva is almost as good as doing it, is
based on God’s omniscience. He takes
them into account when He reviews our deeds, whether they have been completed or
have been left undone because we were unable to perform them fully.
While this concept does not justify rearranging our
lives to focus solely on intent rather than action, it does teach us that when
we perform mitzvot, kavana serves a central role. This idea seems to be expressed
concisely in the Talmudic dictum (Sanhedrin 106b) “God desires the
heart (libba).”
However, alternative sources seem to indicate that
the heart being in the right place is no substitute for the successful
completion of a mitzva. The
Mishna in Pirkei Avot (3:15) states that one is judged according
to the sum of one’s deeds. There is
no mention of an individual’s desires to perform more.
This contradiction gives rise to a rather important
question. Are our successes in the
spiritual realm judged by output or input?
Is our intent more important than our achievement of the desired goal, or
is the reverse true? The Chafetz
Chayim explains this by examining the statement made in Berakhot (28b),
recited as part of the Hadran prayer upon concluding a major unit of
Torah, that those who study Torah toil and receive a reward, while other do not:
clearly all people are rewarded for their hard work, but only a Jew is rewarded
even without the successful completion of his or her attempted goal. The Jew’s input, intent, and planning
are viewed as meritorious even if success is not the ultimate result. Is it really so simple that we are
judged by our heart, libba, and not by our action, maaseh?
One explanation offered for the apparent
inconsistency between these two statements is that while G-d in fact desires the
intent of the heart more than action, the only way to prove whether in fact the
heart is in the right place is to see what actions it motivates the person to
do.
Analyzing the sources we are about to see might
point in another direction as well: one might venture to say that these two
statements refer to two different categories of mitzvot. Mitzvot bein adam la-Makom
seem to be the model of the mitzvot we have been discussing until now, in
which the heart takes priority.
These seem to be mitzvot which have an essential component of intent, and
if a person is under duress, intent may even be sufficient to be viewed as
accomplishment. Mitzvot
bein adam le-chavero, on the other hand, seem to be focused on the result. It is not enough for a person to
intend to be good to his or her friend; one’s actions are judged only by the
bottom line: has a person succeeded in doing good? In fact, the sources seem to go one
step further. Not only is a person
not judged by intent, but the motivation may in fact be unnecessary for
fulfilling the commandment. In addition, one may violate certain prohibitions
between man and his fellow man even if one’s heart is in the right place.
What is the source of our contention that mitzvot
bein adam le-chavero are results-based? First
let us take a look at the Torah itself, where we find a fascinating mitzva. Regarding interpersonal
mitzvot, there is already a biblical source indicating that a person can
perform a mitzva without any intent whatsoever: the mitzva of
shikhcha (literally, forgetfulness), leaving one’s bundles in the field for
the poor. One who, during the
process of harvesting his field, forgets a bundle there is bidden to leave the
produce there for the poor, and the farmer fulfills a mitzva even without
having acted intentionally. “When
you reap the harvest in your field and you forget a bundle in the field, you
shall not turn back to take it; it shall be for the stranger, the orphan, and
the widow” (Devarim 24:19).
When the orphan and widow take the forgotten bundle, the owner of the field
fulfills the mitzva of shikhcha, even if he is unaware that the bundle
has been taken.
The Midrash does not limit this fascinating novelty
to shikhcha, but applies it to tzedaka, charity, as well. Some
authorities go further and express this element as a component of all mitzvot
bein adam le-chavero, as we shall currently see.
Yalkut Shimoni (Torah 937) learns from the verse
regarding the forgotten bundle, that “if an individual loses a coin which is
subsequently found by a poor man who uses it to feed his family, the Torah
considers it as if the one who dropped the coin has provided for the indigent.”
Unlike the sources which we quoted earlier, which
speak of the importance of desire and proper intent of the heart, here the Torah
is crediting an unknowing individual, who may be wondering about the whereabouts
of the money that fell from his pocket, with having supported the needy because
his lost money was found by a pauper.
In fact, not only is it clear that the mitzva has been fulfilled
here without requiring kavana for the action of giving tzedaka, it
has been fulfilled without any intentional action at all! Clearly, the individual did not
intend to lose his money; he would thus fall into the category of mitasek.
Without ever having intent for his action
at all, he is viewed as fulfilling a divine command.
Certainly this is not meant to belittle the
importance of proper intent in the fulfillment of mitzvot involving one’s
fellow man, as the Yalkut Shimoni itself concludes: “If the Torah rewards one
who has no intent, how much more so must the one who intends to give to the poor
be regarded highly!”
Nevertheless, the intent seems to give a person
extra credit only. At the same time,
the best intentions do not seem to be viewed with much approbation if they do
not culminate in an achievement.
While one might want to limit this phenomena of
unknowingly performing mitzvot to giving charity alone, which of course
bears a striking resemblance to shikhcha, it is clear that some
authorities assume otherwise. They
understand the shikhcha phenomenon not as a deviation from the norm, but
as an expression of the nature of all mitzvot bein adam le-chavero.
Rav Elchanan Wasserman (Kovetz Shiurim II,
23:6) points out that there are two general categories of mitzvot: those
which focus on man’s action and those which focus on the result (and therefore,
instead of requiring kavana, require a proper execution of the act). The same distinction, he explains, is
found in negative mitzvot.
Some prohibitions may be violated only by one who has malicious intent, while
others may be violated if an individual’s actions bring about an undesired
outcome. The examples Rav Elchanan
brings for results-centered mitzvot are primarily mitzvot between
persons.
Rav Yosef Engel, in his work Atvan De-Oraita
(13), expresses this distinction even more clearly. He explains that the fundamental
distinction between mitzvot bein adam le-chavero and mitzvot bein adam
la-Makom is in this area.
Mitzvot bein adam la-Makom are, as the name indicates, obligations of man
towards God; man is bidden to prove his desire to fulfill G-d’s will. As long as the proper attempt has
been made, the failure to actually execute the mitzva is irrelevant. On the other hand, mitzvot bein
adam le-chavero are results-based.
The Torah wants man to be beneficent to his fellow; therefore, the
mitzva is judged by the upshot, by the metric of success. (Rav Engel indicates that there are
some mitzvot bein adam la-Makom which are also results-based, but he
refers to them as mitzvot bein adam le-chavero. This idea is also
expressed in Yabbia Omer EH 1:3 and many other sources.)
The implications of this distinction are vast. God’s directive to man to serve Him
focuses on intent, while the instructions regarding how to treat one’s fellow
man seek to ensure that the other actually accrues the benefits God
desires for him. Rav Chayim
Shmuelevitz (Sichot Musar 74) explains that the directive of the Torah to
remember that which happened to Miriam in the desert after she spoke ill of her
brother (Deuteronomy 24:9) is supposed to be a daily reminder that when it comes
to one’s fellow man, righteous intentions do not save one from punishment if the
resulting actions bring about damage.
Miriam only intended well in her speaking about her brother, Moshe, but
damaging speech cannot be permitted no matter how well-meaning the speaker is.
Rav Shmuelevitz goes on to explain that this is the
meaning behind the statement of the Talmud (Bava Batra 16a) that despite
the fact that Peninna, the wife of Elkana who was blessed with ten children,
intended well when she prodded her childless co-wife Channa, she was still
punished (I Shemuel 1-2). The
proper mindset and even righteous intent offer no protection against the
punishment due for the hurt caused to another.
Peninna may have intended to stimulate Channa to pray more strongly; in
fact, she succeeded in doing this.
Nevertheless, Peninna hurt Channa in the process, and she was punished severely
by the death of her own children. In
mitzvot bein adam le-chavero, the ends do not justify the hurtful means.
(See Sichot Musar loc. cit., where he brings a number of other examples
that bear out this point.)
In fact, one might explain the Mishna’s statement in
Pirkei Avot (5:2) that an ignoramus cannot be a kind individual in the
following way: not only must one who strives for righteousness be knowledgeable
in the law, but he must also be knowledgeable in human nature. All too often, we see individuals
with the best of intentions who unknowingly and unintentionally damage others,
such as one who organizes a tzedaka campaign for a friend without
realizing that the friend does not want public charity.
With this in mind, we can start to understand how
the distinction between these two categories of mitzvot indicates that
the address of the action is not their only disparity. These are in fact two alternative
categories, one of divine mandates aimed at man showing his desire to fulfill
the will of G-d through action, and a second of divine mandates aimed at
actually achieving the results of creating a more loving, giving society and
averting damage and hurt from one’s fellow man.
In fact, the laws of these two disparate categories
seem to further bear out this distinction in an enlightening manner.
Rectifying Violations of Mitzvot Bein Adam La-Makom and Bein
Adam Le-chavero:
In the process of teshuva (repentance), one
seeks to repair the damage of sinful behavior.
There are two main distinctions between mitzvot bein adam la-Makom
and mitzvot bein adam le-chavero when it comes to the teshuva
process: the requirements of ritzui
(appeasing the injured party) and public confession. These disparities further
establish the importance of the results-based focus of mitzvot bein adam
le-chavero.
The Rambam (Hilkhot Teshuva 2:9; see Mishna
Yoma 8:9) indicates that Yom Kippur, as well as the standard process of
repentance throughout the year, only serve to absolve a person of sins between
him and God, but not of those between him and his fellow man. In order to atone for sins against
one’s fellow, an individual must first right the wrong by either making
restitution for the loss or fixing the damage caused, and then one may proceed
to obtain verbal forgiveness from his fellow.
The Rambam even uses the term ritzui, a word denoting a
reÂcreation of comity and unity, not only a willingness to forgive as part of
the teshuva process. Only
after the damage has been rectified and unity re-created can an individual then
attempt to continue his teshuva process for violating a mitzva bein
adam le-chavero vis-Ã -vis God Himself.
According to our understanding that mitzvot
bein adam le-chavero are results-oriented, we may clearly explain the
necessity of righting a wrong done to one’s friend and obtaining his
forgiveness. Even if one has seen
the error of his ways and wants to repent, as long as the damage is still there,
creating a distance between two Jews in place of the camaraderie the Torah
desires, then the prohibition is still being violated. Only a reversal of the damage can
open the gates for an individual to cleanse himself from the sin to his fellow.
This idea is further expressed in the Rambam’s
understanding of the need for public confession of one’s sins. He writes (Hilkhot Teshuva
2:5) that it is proper that one who violates interpersonal commandments confess
publicly, while one who violates obligations bein adam la-Makom needs to
confess privately only. The
explanation of the distinction seems to be based on the premise which we have
discussed. Sins against one’s fellow
damage not only the victim; the harm is magnified by the way it is seen by the
public. An act of apology and
confession that does not rectify the public harm done to the wronged individual
is deficient. In contrast,
mitzvot bein adam le-Makom, with their intent-oriented focus, are
meant to remain between man and G-d. (In the upcoming lesson, we will elaborate
regarding the process of forgiveness for interpersonal violations.)
The Lack of a Berakha for Mitzvot Bein Adam Le-chavero:
With this in mind, let us conclude our discussion by
examining a final discrepancy between mitzvot bein adam la-Makom and
mitzvot bein adam le-chavero: the need for a berakha (blessing) prior
to the fulfillment of most of the former type.
This is what we refer to as birkat ha-mitzva, the blessing made
over a commandment, which usually consists of the standard opening, followed by
the phrase “asher kiddeshanu be-mitzvotav ve-tzivanu,” “Who has
sanctified us with His commandments and commanded us”, concluding with the title
or action of the mitzva.
While many mitzvot bein adam la-Makom require a birkat ha-mitzva,
no mitzva bein adam le-chavero does.
In fact, the Rambam (Hilkhot Berakhot 11:2) only mentions the
concept of a birkat ha-mitzva in conjunction with mitzvot bein
adam la-Makom, as if to say there is no room for a berakha on
interpersonal mitzvot. Why
not?
We noted in the previous lecture that even though
human beings may have a natural sense of morality, God sees it fit to command us
to perform mitzvot bein adam le-chavero. It would seem that an
individual should make a berakha prior to their performance, just as one
does with most mitzvot.
However, this is not the case, and the commentators discuss this seeming
anomaly. While a complete
understanding of this issue would require a more clear definition of the purpose
of a birkat ha-mitzva, our earlier discussion will shed light on the
topic. We will focus on three primary explanations; that of the Rashba, who
focuses on the significance of the results; that of the Or Zarua, who expounds
the significance of limitations in applicability; and that of the commentators
who focus on the uniqueness of the commandment for these mitzvot.
The lack of a birkat ha-mitzva for mitzvot
bein adam le-chavero is already discussed in a responsum of the Rashba (I,
18), who explains:
One does not make a blessing on an action that is
not completely in the hands of the performer because it is possible that the one
on whose behalf the action is being performed may reject it, thus negating it. This includes gifts to the poor,
loans, charity, etc.
The Rashba’s explanation is clearly understood in
the context of our premise. Actions
done on behalf of one’s fellow man are results-based. In order to warrant a berakha
prior to its performance, a mitzva’s successful realization must be exclusively
in the hands of the person doing it.
The performance of a mitzva bein adam la-Makom is completely in the hands
of the doer, because it focuses on the intent of the one taking action to follow
the will of God. In contrast,
mitzvot bein adam le-chavero, such as giving charity and making loans, do
not reach their fulfillment unless they are accepted by the recipient. Therefore, a birkat ha-mitzva
is not applicable to them. The Rashba’s distinction seems to be a source from
the Rishonim for our understanding that the successful completion of mitzvot
between man and his fellow are dependent on the intended recipient’s acceptance
of the doer’s action.
While the explanation of the Rashba seems to confirm
our distinction between the two types of mitzvot quite clearly, other
answers provided by commentators on this subject seem to open the door for next
lesson’s discussion. This is because
of the unique way in which they underscore the singularity of mitzvot bein
adam le-chavero.
The Or Zarua (Hilkhot Birkat Hamotzi 140)
writes that one does not make a birkat ha-mitzva for any obligation which
is unceasing and constant. He
includes within his list the mitzvot of chesed.
The Or Zarua seems to be explaining that a birkat
ha-mitzva is necessary when an individual stops what he is doing to
discharge an obligation which arises at that given moment. In contrast, chesed is
ubiquitous and perpetual. A
birkat ha-mitzva indicates that the mitzva’s setting is limited, so a
berakha cannot be made for a constant mitzva such as chesed.
We aren’t supposed to switch on the “be nice” button when it suits us – kindness
is supposed to be a constant endeavor. Accordingly, we should not say that
mitzvot bein adam le-chavero do not deserve a berakha; rather, making
a berakha would almost demean them by implying that the time for kindness
is a particular moment, rather than always.
A number of other commentaries focus on the
inapplicability of the text of the standard birkat ha-mitzva,
particularly the word “ve-tzivanu”, for a variety of reasons.
The 16th-century scholar Rav Binyamin Ben
Matitya (Responsa Binyamin Ze’ev 169) explains that the universal
nature of mitzvot bein adam le-chavero is what precludes us from saying a
berakha before performing them.
The text of a berakha specifies the uniqueness of the mitzva
to the Jewish people (“ve-tzivanu” — “and commanded us”), but
mitzvot of kindness and the like performed on behalf of one’s fellow man
are applicable worldwide; therefore, they do not deserve a birkat ha-mitzva
celebrating our uniqueness. (A similar idea is mentioned by the Torah Temima,
Shemot 24:30.)
In a slightly different way, the Arukh Ha-shulchan (CM
427:10) explains that while our obligation in mitzvot bein adam le-chavero
is indeed unique in its breadth and scope, the universal applicability hides the
sanctity in these mitzvot; therefore, they are not accompanied by a
berakha. Our chesed may
not be the same as kindness amongst the nations, but since that is not readily
apparent, we do not make a berakha.
While these explanations seem to focus on the lack
of uniqueness in our system of mitzvot bein adam le-chavero, a second
look may indicate quite the opposite.
There is a universal appeal and applicability to kindness, but as the
Arukh Ha-shulchan formulates it, this only serves to conceal the uniquely Jewish
nature of chesed. God chooses
to order us to fulfill these mitzvot despite the fact that we could
figure many of them out on our own.
The divine command actually serves to differentiate our mitzvot bein adam
le-chavero from the moral codes of the rest of the world, as it
simultaneously makes the singularity of the mitzvot bein adam le-chavero
less readily apparent.
Why does God choose to command us and sanctify us
through His commandments in the form of mitzvot that we might have
decided to do without a divine command?
Rav Yechiel Yaakov Weinberg’s comments on this issue
may shed light on this peculiarity.
He writes (Responsa Seridei Eish I:61) that the rationale for not
being able to make a birkat ha-mitzva and to say “ve-tzivanu” is
not the lack of uniqueness of the directive; rather, it is because we are
required to perform the commandment with an inner desire, not out of compulsion. One should not give charity
begrudgingly, simply because it is demanded of us, but out of an honest feeling
of wanting to provide for one’s fellow and to achieve the desired result that
the mitzva sets out to accomplish.
With this in mind, we have seemingly come full
circle. Despite the natural,
universal application of the results-oriented mitzvot bein adam le-chavero,
there is clearly a unique expression provided by the divine command to the Jew. Its uniqueness might be hidden to the
outsider, but only an in-depth study of the halakhic requirements
involved in each mitzva will serve to reveal its true nature and purpose. The divine imperative seems to
express the uniqueness of the Jewish social ideal; simultaneously it lends an
aspect of mitzvot bein adam la-Makom to every mitzva bein adam
le-chavero.
In fact, regarding our discussion of repentance, the
fact that one must also perform teshuva before God (see Hilkhot
Teshuva 1:1 and 2:11) for a violation of a mitzva bein adam le-chavero
seems to indicate that there is an element of divine will within the very
mitzva, an aspect of bein adam la-Makom. Why is this necessary, and what does
it mean? We shall see in the next
lesson.
In the upcoming shiur we will address these
questions while further developing an understanding of a third type of mitzva,
mitzvot bein adam le-atzmo (intrapersonal commandments). I will attempt to show how all
mitzvot bein adam le-chavero carry within them elements of all three
types of mitzvot. I hope to
further define these three types of mitzvot and delineate the various
aspects of each mitzva.